It's a
great question which a friend and I were discussing over a group dinner Friday
night. I can offer plenty of suggestions to whet your appetite; there are
numerous ideas that would enrich people's understanding of everyday societal
matters that are not currently captured with enough depth to do so. Examples would be things
like comparative advantage, that which is seen and unseen, deadweight costs,
Coase's theorem, Chesterton's fence and the concept of the invisible hand. Then
there are absolutely life-changing ideas such as Aumann's
Agreement Theorem and Harsanyi's
Amnesia Principle that bear repeating regularly to get them as widely
disseminated as possible. All of those ideas make an appearance in this blog
from time to time.
However, the
idea I'll pick as the idea of choice in response to this blog post's title will
be Arrow's Theorem, as a tribute to Kenneth Arrow who died this week. He was,
up until a few days ago, one of the greatest living economists. Arrow's Theorem
is not the easiest to describe simplistically because it is mathematically
dense, and is quite counterintuitive too (I had a go once
before using voting as the illustrative template). In fact, past reading of
economics has given me the impression that several economist social commentators
have described Arrow's Theorem as the hardest complex idea to simplify for a
layperson. I'll have a try with a version I typed up yesterday in the hope that
you find it both understandable and intriguing.
To do so, let's discuss my
favourite dessert - cheesecake. What I'm going to illustrate is that no democratic
system, however fair it appears in terms of participants and number of choices,
can satisfy all the axioms associated with the preferences. So for example, if
there are three, then: if two are satisfied the third must be violated, whether
those two are 1 and 2, 2 and 3, or 1 and 3.
Let's illustrate
this. Every day, Julie, Frank and Timothy split a cheesecake with one flavour -
Chocolate, Strawberries or Lemon. Their preference orderings change from day to
day - some days Julie is in the mood for Strawberries, other days the very
thought of Strawberries makes her wish she was eating another flavoured
cheesecake. Every evening at dinner time they have to call in their first,
second and third choice cheesecake orders (let's say the cheesecake patisserie
insists that you specify your second and third choices in case they run out of
something.) So Julie, Frank and Timothy need a method for translating their
individual preferences to a cheesecake order. Now as it happens, on the 22nd on
February, their preferences ran as follows:
Julie
|
Frank
|
Timothy
|
|
First Choice
|
Chocolate
|
Strawberries
|
Lemon
|
Second Choice
|
Strawberries
|
Lemon
|
Chocolate
|
Third Choice
|
Lemon
|
Chocolate
|
Strawberries
|
I’m not
going to divulge what system these three were using to determine their order,
but I will tell you that on the 22nd they phoned the patisserie and expressed Chocolate
as their first choice. On the 23rd, Julie ranked Chocolate over Lemon again
(and let's suppose we don’t know anything about Frank’s or Timothy’s rankings).
On the 22nd, only Julie ranked Chocolate over Lemon, whereas on the 23rd, Julie
plus possibly one or both of the others ranked Chocolate over Lemon. So if the
cheesecake order ranked Chocolate above Lemon on the 22nd, then it should
certainly have ranked Chocolate over Lemon on the 23rd, no?
In
principle, yes (disallowing for a change of mind for variety - not something
that's as likely to happen in political voting). Any other result would have
seemed unreasonable to Julie, Frank and Timothy, so when they designed their
system, they designed it with the following feature. If we list Chocolate over
Lemon on our order on one day, and if none of the people who prefer Chocolate
over Lemon change their minds about that the next day, then we should list Chocolate
over Lemon the next day as well.
Because
this was implicit in their system (and because they’d listed Chocolate over
Lemon on the 22nd when only Julie had that preference), they always listed Chocolate
over Lemon on any day when Julie preferred Chocolate to Lemon. That is to say,
Julie was the principal figure on the Chocolate/Lemon consideration - the 'authoritarian', if you like.
Now on the
24th, Julie was in a Chocolate/Lemon/Strawberries frame of mind. Suppose again
we don't know much about Frank’s or Timothy’s moods except that they both favoured
Lemon over Strawberries. Since everyone preferred Lemon to Strawberries, Lemon
was, of course, listed higher than Strawberries in the cheesecake hierarchy.
Once again, any other result would have appeared unreasonable to Julie, Frank
and Timothy, so they’d built their system along the following lines:
Whenever we unanimously prefer option
X to option Y, option X should rank higher than option Y on our order.
First,
Julie preferred Chocolate to Lemon, so of course Chocolate ranked higher than
Lemon. Second, everyone preferred Lemon to Strawberries, so Lemon ranked higher
than Strawberries. Logic says that Chocolate must have ranked higher than Strawberries.
Logic also says that when Julie prefers Chocolate/Lemon/Strawberries in that
order, and everyone else prefers Lemon to Strawberries, Chocolate must be more preferable
than Strawberries.
They also
agreed the following:
Our
preferences regarding Lemon should not affect the relative positions of Chocolate
and Strawberries in the ranking. Therefore, the above should hold if we drop
all the Lemon-related assumptions. That is to say, on any day when Julie
prefers Chocolate to Strawberries, Chocolate must rank higher than Strawberries.
The next
day, the 25th, Julie’s preferences ran Strawberries/Chocolate/Lemon, while the
other two both preferred Strawberries to Chocolate. Since they all preferred Strawberries
to Chocolate, Strawberries came out higher than Chocolate on the cheesecake order.
Since Julie was a Chocolate/Lemon authoritarian, Chocolate came out higher than
Lemon. Logic tells us also that Strawberries came out higher than Lemon. And
the same would be true on any day when Julie preferred Strawberries/Chocolate/Lemon
and everyone else preferred Strawberries to Chocolate.
But the
ranking of Strawberries vs. Lemon was designed to be unaffected by how anyone
cared about Chocolate, so the Chocolate-related information cannot be relevant.
This tells us that on any day when Julie prefers Strawberries to Lemon, Strawberries
rank higher than Lemon. She’s not just a Chocolate/Lemon authoritarian and a
Chocolate/Strawberries authoritarian; she’s a Strawberries/Lemon authoritarian
too.
What we’ve uncovered
is that any Chocolate/Lemon authoritarian is also a Chocolate/Strawberries authoritarian
and a Strawberries/Lemon authoritarian. Interchanging the flavours, we could have
just as easily discovered that any Chocolate/Strawberries authoritarian (e.g. Julie)
is also a Chocolate/Lemon and a Lemon/Strawberries authoritarian - and so on as
every pair of flavours appear. In other words, despite the table of preferences
above, Julie is an absolute cheesecake authoritarian as all of her preferences
are entirely reflected in the cheesecake order on any given day.
Now here's
the upshot of it all. We started by declaring that Chocolate came out on top on
the 22nd. But if Strawberries had come out on top, then using Arrow's model I
could have given evidence to show that Frank is an absolute authoritarian, and
if Lemon had come out on top, then using Arrow's model I could have given
evidence to show that Timothy is an absolute authoritarian. Regardless of what
happened on the 22nd, someone must be an absolute authoritarian -
counterintuitive as that may have first appeared.
Extending
that further, if there had been more people than just Julie, Frank and Timothy,
and more flavours than Chocolate, Strawberries and Lemon, then although the
argument becomes more mathematically intractable, it is not at heart any further
from the nub of the wisdom just covered - that is, if you have a scenario that
translates a series of individual preference choices into a single group
preference of choice, that scenario will throw up an authoritarian.
Crucially here, we're
seeing the distinction between what are very coherent individual preferences
(called transitivity), and how at a group level it becomes incoherent (intransitivity). Transitivity is formally
expressed as: if A > B, and B > C, then A > C - so in other words, with
cheesecake choices, if Julie likes Chocolate more than Strawberries and
Strawberries more than Lemon, she should like Chocolate more than Lemon.
Groups, however, don't necessarily
have a transitive preference order - they have intransitive 'cycling' of
preferences, which means Chocolate beats Strawberries, which beats Lemon, which
beats Chocolate, which beats Strawberries, which beats Lemon, which beats
Chocolate - meaning for group scenarios you might just as well put the flavours
of cheesecake in a hat.
No comments:
Post a Comment