Every married couple knows
that the most important question of all isn't 'Why is there something rather than nothing?", or "What is reality?" or "Will we ever fully understand
consciousness?" - it is this epic question:
"Should men put the toilet seat down after they'd
had a wee?"
I jotted down some
thoughts, and my friend Tim Reeves commented. For anyone interested, here is
our discussion:
Toilet Seat Economics
JK: You know the scene;
Jack and Jill get married, and they have that discussion about what the toilet
seat policy should be in the marital home. Jill usually says "Please leave
it down after you use it", and Jack can respond in different ways. He can
refuse in a carefree way (that's not going to help the relationship), he can
acquiesce in a resentful way (that's not the best response either), he can
refuse in a logical way (more on that in a moment) or he can acquiesce in a
cooperative way because he loves her. One of the latter two ways is best - and
I'm going to explore which one it is.
This kind of
scenario is often thought of in terms of game theory strategy - but husbands
who think this way are making an amateur mistake. In game theory, a
state called the Nash equilibrium occurs when no agent in a situation can
improve their strategy by unilaterally changing their actions. The optimal
outcome of a situation is where there is no incentive to deviate from the
initial strategy once he or she knows their opponent's decision. In the well
known prisoner's dilemma, for example, the Nash equilibrium is not for both of
you to remain silent. The Nash equilibrium in the prisoner's dilemma is for
both you and Jill to betray each other, because even though mutually staying
silent leads to a better outcome, if one chooses betrayal and the other stays
silent, one of you has a worse outcome. In other words, the rational decision
is to betray, because betraying can't make your situation worse, but it might
make it better.
This also shows that
rational decisions don't always lead to good outcomes. Imagine you're Jack. If
Jill betrays you and you remain silent, you get three years in prison by not
betraying Jill, and two years in prison by betraying her. Therefore it's better
for you if you betray Jill. If Jill stays silent and you betray Jill you walk
free, and if you also remain silent you receive one year in prison. Therefore
it's still better if you betray Jill, and the Nash equilibrium occurs if you
both betray each other. However, a husband and wife with a healthy relationship
are a cooperative unit, not in competition, so Nash equilibria does not apply
here, because it only applies when two agents are in competition.
TR: Agreed. What is
“rational” here really depends on whether or not we are dealing with a single
organism or two competing organisms. For organically joined players the cooperative
strategy is the rational one, but for two separate competing organisms betrayal
is the rational choice.
JK: And thankfully,
married life need not be like a prisoner's dilemma - it should be an
opportunity to bless each other, although sometimes the mathematics is fun too.
To see why the toilet seat issue is an even bigger chance to bless each other
than is often realised, let's assume for a second that the husband and wife are
treating the toilet seat issue in a competitive prisoner's dilemma-style
scenario. In competition, where the strategy is to touch the toilet seat as
infrequently as possible, you'll find that acquiescing to the lady's request to
always leave the toilet seat down is inefficient. Leaving the toilet seat the
same as after you've used it is the most efficient system.
Here's why. If you leave
it always down then any time the man goes consecutively he is inconvenienced by
having to move it up again, even though he used it last. Similarly if you leave
it always up, any time the woman goes consecutively she is inconvenienced by
having to move it down again. Leaving it always down is inefficient to males;
leaving it always up is inefficient to females; and leaving as you used it the
most efficient system.
But we are only looking at
this situation from the perspective of minimising the joint total cost, where
cost is touching the toilet seat unnecessarily. The mathematics is fairly easy
to enumerate on this: assuming for simplicity that both Jack and Jill use the
toilet exactly the same number of times, then if both Jack and Jill leave the
seat up every time they use it, both will touch it the most, and Jill will
touch it about six times more than Jack, making it the least efficient of all.
If the decision was decided by a coin toss, then both Jack and Jill should
touch it roughly equal number of times, but they will jointly touch it the
second most occurrences.
If Jack leaves it the
opposite of how he found it, he will touch it about 75% of the time, and Jill
25% of the time; If Jill leaves the opposite of how she found it, she will
touch it about 75% of the time, and Jack 25% of the time - and in both cases
they will jointly touch it less than the two cases above. The last option
though - leaving it as you last used it - is the most efficient way to minimise
the joint total cost. Because Jill only needs it down, and Jack needs it both
up and down, he will touch it a little more often than Jill will, but they will
both jointly touch it the least often.
However, all this only
factors in the scenario that Jack and Jill go equally and alternatively. If we
allow for the fact that for all sorts of reasons, like different liquid
consumption, and different times they are in the house, there will be many
times when Jack and Jill will go consecutively, and that's even stronger
argument for leaving it as you last used it. Take an extreme case: suppose Jack
drinks lots of water and goes to urinate 5 times for every 1 time that Jill
goes, then a policy in which he put the seat down every time for Jill means he
is putting it down and then back up again 4 times, with him being the only one
who has used it during that time.
Conclusion: leaving it as
you last used it is the best policy for Jack and Jill.
Now, here's the rub: it's
not quite that simple, because love is about more than logical reasoning - it
is about putting each other first. A couple whose strategy was simply to
minimise the joint total costs would quite naturally adopt the policy of leaving
the toilet seat as you last used it.
TR: Conventional
water closets get visited by two kinds of people. Namely “Down Persons” (=D)
and “Up Persons”. You notice that I haven’t distinguished between male and
female. When a male goes to the toilet he can be in either an “up” state or a
“down” state; so as far as toilet usage is concerned he’s two different people
in the up state and down states. Because we are thinking of the overall organic
economy of the household we need not make the distinction between male and
female just yet; in fact it’s a distraction from the core mathematics. So if we
assume that Up and Down persons visit the cubicle in some pattern of visits we
can represent that pattern as something like this:
DDDDDUDDUUDDDUDDDDDUDDDDDUUUD….etc
The
troublesome configurations are the pairs UD and DU as they entail the
expenditure of energy and time by the household in order to change the state of
the toilet seat. Interesting to note that it doesn’t matter who puts the seat
up or down as the expenditure in energy & time is the same. A D-person could put the seat up in advance
just prior to the visit of a U-person. Or alternatively a U person visiting the
cubicle could put the seat up after a D person has used it. (It’s contrariwise
for the configuration UD, of course) The point is that in terms of time and
energy it doesn’t make any difference whether U or D makes the necessary
changes to the state of the toilet seat.
But there is
a big “but” with what I have just said: It assumes that the pattern of visits
is predictable to the extent that a householder knows whether the next visitor
is an Up or a Down. This assumption, of course breaks down if the pattern of
visits is random, in which case a cubicle user will not know whether the next
user is U or D.
So what is
the most household efficient strategy if the pattern is random? In this case
the householder doesn’t know whether the next visitor is a U or a D. Hence if a
householder changes the state of the seat after using it in preparation for the
next visitor this may well be wasted time and energy, because the next visitor
who comes in at random may have to wastefully change its state back to what it
was. Because a user cannot anticipate whether the next user is a D or a U that
user is not the best person to change the state of the seat because that state
may have to be undone. The best person is of course the next person who visits
the cubicle because they obviously know their requirements best and therefore
no tricky precognition is needed by the previous visitor!
So to summarise, I agree that your strategy, which involves the last visitor leaving the toilet seat in the state he/she used it, is the most efficient scenario timewise and energetically.
JK: Moving on from mere
economic efficiency to blissful marriage efficiency, a good strategy would be
to supersede the good strategy with a better strategy whereby the husband
insists on putting the toilet seat down for his wife. One objection might be
that if the basis of a successful marriage is for each to put the other one
first, then letting Jack put the toilet seat down every time is to make him
complicit in an erroneous cost-benefit scenario, and that is not really an
example of Jill putting his needs first.
TR: I’d go
along with the general sentiment here that if “putting the other first” leads
to wasteful inefficient scenarios it’s not actually that “loving”. After all,
the overall household economy affects both players and if wasteful practices
are adopted all parties can be adversely affected in the long term. So we are
looking for efficient cooperative strategies. However there are other factors at work.
Toilet seat changes involve very little energy and time and so the extra energy
and time used by, say, U putting the seat down for D may perhaps be worthwhile
for relationship purposes and help cement ties which could be of overwhelming
concern in an organic whole that depends on
a cooperative household economy.
JK: The way to optimise
this situation in accordance with mutual regard for the other, then, is to have
a discussion with your beloved and agree on what is most important to them
about this scenario, and who cares the most (because it will vary couple to
couple). Because economics is primarily a study of human behaviour, and human
behaviour is conditioned by our feelings, then your optimal system in the
marital home must factor in levels of importance for each beloved. For example,
in a typical marriage I'd predict that a lady cares a lot more about not having
to touch the toilet seat than a man does about having to lift it up, so the
most maritally efficient, and therefore also the most economically efficient in
this case, is for Jack to show love and put it down after use, for Jill to love
him gratefully in return for doing so, and for her to forgive him if he forgets
from time to time, because she knows his intentions are the best for her.