Qualities in life - be
they ability, money, looks - have both an absolute value and a relative value.
Let’s take wealth; your absolute wealth is the intrinsic gains and losses that
occur in your own finances, whereas your relative wealth is how those gains and
losses are perceived in relation to others.
Everyone can appreciate
the changes in their own absolute wealth. If your first effort as a novelist
earns you £250,000 you'll be happy. If it earns you £350,000 you'll be happier
still. Sometimes, though, your views on absolute wealth change when presented
with different comparisons related to relative wealth. For example, suppose you
were looking for the balance between financial rewards and critical acclaim -
and for simplicity’s sake let's suppose you're never going to write another
novel again, meaning that critical acclaim or critical derogation won't affect
future publishing potential. Consider the following choice:
Scenario 1
Option A) £350,000 and worldwide critical derogation Option B) £250,000 and worldwide critical acclaim
In the above scenario
you would choose option B if your value of critical acclaim (and the corollary,
your aversion to derogation) exceeds £100,000. If your value of critical
acclaim is less than the difference between A and B then you’d choose option A.
Let’s suppose from now on that you value critical acclaim at £35,000, you would
opt for option A in the above scenario.
Now let's look at two
more different scenarios, where you value critical acclaim at £35,000. Consider the following choice:
Scenario 2
Option A) £375,000 and no critical acclaimOption B) £350,000 and critical acclaim
In scenario 2 you should
choose B because the value of the sum earned (£350,000) plus the value of
critical acclaim to you (£35,000) amounts to £385,000, making it more
favourable than option A, which at £375,000 is worth £10,000 less. Most people
who valued critical acclaim at £35,000 would, I suspect, choose option B.
But suppose you still
valued critical acclaim at £35,000 but were given a third scenario:
Scenario 3
Option A) £50,000 and no critical acclaimOption B) £25,000 and critical acclaim
In scenario 3 your
decision should be no different to scenario 2. Nothing has changed in absolute
terms: in scenario 3 the sum of your valuation of critical acclaim (£35,000)
and the earnings (£25,000) amount to £10,000 more than the option A (£50,000).
But I suspect you'd be much less likely to choose option B in scenario 3
because your concern for critical acclaim would reduce your cash earnings by
50%, whereas in scenario 2 it would reduce your cash earnings by just 6.7%.
That is to say, in relative
terms the difference between £25,000 in scenario 2 (6.7%) is a lot less painful
than the difference between £25,000 in scenario 3 (50%) even though the
absolute value doesn't change.
Clearly this is
understandable; a 50% increase from £25,000 or £50,000 can change your life by
a very great amount, whereas if you've obtained the life-changing amount of
£350,000, then that extra £25,000 increase to £375,000 changes your life by
considerably less. This is called the law of diminishing marginal utility, where
the first unit of consumption of a good or service brings about greater utility
than the second unit of consumption, with diminution continuing with more and
more units.
In the above scenario
your relative considerations were not against the earnings of other authors,
they were considerations related to the trade off between earnings and critical
acclaim. Quite often, though, the earnings of others is a big factor in
people’s decisions. Let’s consider a different example, which shows how much
emphasis people place on relative value over absolute value. If given the
following choice:
Option A) You increase
your earnings by £12,000 per year, and all your same-sex friends increase
theirs by £15,000 per year
Option B) You increase your earnings by £11,000 per year, and all your same-sex friends increase theirs by £8,000 per year
Surprisingly, a lot of people would choose option B, because their
relative wealth in comparison to their same-sex friends is more important to
them than an increase of £1,000 in their absolute wealth if their friends'
absolute wealth increases by more.
I think this is irrational. £1,000 is still as valuable to you in
monetary terms irrespective of whether your friends increase their absolute
wealth by £8,000 or £15,000. Only if your social status is more valuable to you
than £1000 should you choose option B - but I think it'd be a sorry thing if
you valued social status that much.
Here's another example - this time an example of how humans are
irrational when faced with different numbers.
Scenario 1
You are about to buy a
specialised pair of welding gloves for £60 in Lewisham, when an app pops up on
your phone telling you that at a shop in the centre of London the welding
gloves are £30 cheaper (that's a £30 saving even after Tube costs and additional
time have been factored in as well).
If you asked 1000 people if they would go into London to make that saving, many would, as
it's a 50% discount. Now here's a variation on that question.
Scenario 2
You are about to buy a
brand new Nissan Micra for £1499 in Lewisham - but in the centre of London the
same car company has the exact same car that will cost you £1469 (that's also a
saving of £30, again with Tube fare and additional time factored in).
Suppose every other detail is the same except the relative nature
of the £30 saving, I'll wager that if you asked 1000 people whether they'd now
bother to head into the centre of London
to save £30 on a Nissan Micra, most would say no.
Given the relative infrequency with which we buy a new car, there
should be no difference in the two options - if you value the £30 saving on the
first product you should value it on the second product too - but almost no one
does, because relative to £1499 a £30 saving is nothing like a saving relative to £60.
After putting questions like this out there for public
consideration I've also found that people are often irrationally more cautious
with large numbers than small numbers, even if the same probability occurs in
both situations. For example, suppose I gave the average person the following
scenario:
Option A) You have a big
bag with 1 black ball and 999 white balls inside. You get to pull one ball out;
if it's black you die, if it's white you get £1 million pounds.
In that scenario most people would feel pretty confident and
probably take up the offer. Suppose now I gave the average person this scenario:
Option B) You have a
very big bag with 1000 black balls inside and 999,000 white balls inside. You
get to pull one ball out; if it's black you die, if it's white you get £1
million pounds.
Regarding Option B, my results overwhelmingly show that people
would be more cautious than with Option A even though the probability is the
same. In fact, I fancy that if you gave 1000 people Option A, got them to
choose to take part or not, then wiped their memories of Option A and proceeded
to give them Option B, a large number would give a different answer.
When it comes to things like wealth inequality in the world,
humans still tend to be much more interested in relative wealth than absolute
wealth. The trouble is, unless this is done sensibly it causes people to forget
arithmetic and to think irrationally. My advice is that unless there is a jolly
good reason for thinking relatively, people should get into the habit of
thinking in terms of absolute gains and losses, and not be anchored by how
those absolute gains measure relative to other people's absolute gains.
No comments:
Post a Comment