Now apply that to bankers pitching for their own successes. Just as you don't need to pay car boot sellers with lots of quality goods to sell, you don't need to pay bankers with lots of business acumen and financial nous inflated salaries to perform well. To get them to make good decisions, you only need to give them share-based or bonus-based incentives to do what they do best, because their own wealth is tied up in their success.
Using Philosophical and Economic analysis to consider big questions, world issues and matters of everyday life!
Friday, 28 February 2014
Why Bankers' Bonuses Should Be *More*, Not Less
Now apply that to bankers pitching for their own successes. Just as you don't need to pay car boot sellers with lots of quality goods to sell, you don't need to pay bankers with lots of business acumen and financial nous inflated salaries to perform well. To get them to make good decisions, you only need to give them share-based or bonus-based incentives to do what they do best, because their own wealth is tied up in their success.
Thursday, 27 February 2014
Be Encouraged: Why Writing Blogs Is A Bit Like Publishing Books
There are perhaps 3 main rewards for writers:
Not every writer has number 3, but every writer can have numbers 1 and 2 (in the case of 2, assuming they're any good).
For those for whom number 3 is a bonus and not to be expected, and for those not being paid by newspapers or magazines, 1 and 2 can still be obtained either through writing books and attempting to get them published or through writing Blogs.
Playing around gracefully with hypotheticals, as I often like to do, I wonder what sort of value I (or anyone like me) would place on number 2 in all sorts of scenarios. Suppose there were 50,000 impressed readers reading my Blog for free each week vs. 50 super-duper impressed readers who would pay £2 per week to read my Blog (I doubt it - but humour me). What's better for the writer - all that adulation and no money, or 0.1% of the adulation and £100 per week? What about 100,000 non-paying impressed readers per week vs.100 super-duper impressed readers who would pay £2 per week to read my Blog (earning £200 per week for me) - which of those is preferable to most writers, or is it fairly evenly split? Perhaps the mass adulation would be worth losing £100 per week for but not £200. I don't know. There are lots of other factors too, and I haven't given them a lengthy consideration.
The number 4562 is not insignificant in my deliberations. My Blog reader count is 188,488. If we say that each hit has an average time of 2 minutes, which accounts for those who spend less time per hit and those who spend more, then that amounts to a total of 9124 hours for my aggregate readership. If we say that an average regular size book takes 2 hours to read, then 9124 hours of Blog reading is equivalent to the reading time of 4562 books. Thus, if I take into account only the information shared and the readership interest, then my writing this Philosophical Muser Blog has been roughly equivalent to writing a book that has sold 4562 copies.
As it happens, I am writing books as well, but haven't yet reached the stage of attempted publication. Until then I can dabble in my Blog writing. I wanted to write this to encourage fellow Blog writers, and others writing pro bono and au gratis - if as yet you're happy with the rewards of 1) the personal enrichment that comes from forming your ideas and writing about them, and 2) being able to share your writing and attaining positive public feedback - then what you're doing has some of the rewards of writing a book and having it published, so be encouraged to keep up the good work.
* That's not to say negative feedback isn't valuable - but if we are being truthful, no writer really likes it.
** You may say selling 4562 copies has the added benefit of enhancing your future chances of being published, but consider it may have the opposite effect. Having a first relatively unsuccessful book published might be a springboard to future success, but equally its relative failure might put off any future publishers.
Friday, 21 February 2014
Women Drivers & The Counter-Productive European Court of Justice
My car insurance is due soon. I hadn't kept up with all the arcane ways that EU legislation affects
Tuesday, 18 February 2014
Sometimes 'Life' Should Mean 'Life'
Thursday, 13 February 2014
"Smoking" Gun Evidence of Inconsistency
Monday, 10 February 2014
Why We Never Have, & Never Will, Predict Anything New
Hang on, I hear you protest, of course we predict things, don't
we? We make predictions in everything from carefully studied specialised
subjects like evolutionary biology, to simple sub-conscious predictions like
'tomorrow darkness will follow the day'. This is true, but it's a somewhat
different thing. To understand why we don't predict anything new, you have to
understand what is meant by 'new', and also that what we think are predictions
are actually arrangements of ideas based on prior experiences. So in saying we
never predict anything, what I mean is, we never predict anything that isn't
already part of our repertoire of prior experience.
This was a groundbreaking observation by empiricist philosopher David Hume, and it has never been refuted to this day. Hume drew the distinction between the kind of predictions made from prior experiences (like evolutionary biology and anything related to scientific enquiry) and our inability to know or predict anything that hasn't yet been experienced. This is what he called the difference between 'causality' and 'causation'. With the necessary prior experience we can distil knowledge of cause and effect (causality), but we have no direct intuitive ability to distil a connection between cause and effect (causation) - {don't worry, this will become clearer in a moment}.
Causality
Examples of causality would be something like: apples fall from
the tree because of gravity, or if I bang my head it will hurt. Because of
prior experience of gravity and banging our head, we can predict that when an
apple begins to disconnect itself from the tree it will fall to the ground, and
we can predict that if we bang our head on a low hanging tree branch it will
hurt. But they are assumptions under the classical interpretation of gravity
and solid objects. We could not predict from the classical system that there is
a force of gravity according to the principles of quantum mechanics (quantum
gravity), or that the tree is largely made up of empty space. Experiences of
the quantum world have enabled us to understand gravity and solidity in ways
that augment the Newtonian lens of reality, but without the agency to perceive
the quantum world (empirical experience, scientific apparatus, and so forth),
quantum physics couldn't be predicted.
When Hume says that we can have no direct intuitive ability to distil a connection between cause and effect in terms of causation, he is saying we can’t reason prior to experience anything new about nature*.So to recap, Hume’s contention (with which I concur) was that because we only discover things from past extrapolations, we experience only causality, and not causation - and we have to experience the causality before we can know of causation.
Causation
So what is this 'causation' that we cannot predict or know without
prior experience? I'll try to explain with a couple of simple thought
experiments. Suppose that as of midnight tonight a fundamental fact in the
universe is going to change. While you are sleeping tonight what you thought
was a fundamental law of nature gets changed; from 6am something is altered in
one of nature's multi-dimensions and we no longer can have a magnetic field
through the application of electricity. When you wake up in the morning, you
wouldn't have any way of knowing this before you've climbed out of bed, because
as far as you are concerned nothing has changed. It would be impossible for you
to wake up in the morning and reason your way to the conclusion that it will be
impossible to have a magnetic field through the application of electricity.
But you are about to find out; you get up at 7am with no knowledge of this fundamental change in nature - but as you go about your daily business you start to sense something is wrong, because you notice subtle empirical indications. What empirical indications do you notice? You turn on the radio and the electromagnets that used to amplify the sound coming out of the speakers no longer do what they did yesterday. The postman rings the doorbell but nothing happens except silence. When he pushed the button, where a tiny electromagnet would pull a metal clapper against a bell, now there is no sound at all. You decide to pull it apart - you examine the length of conductive copper wire wrapped around the metal, you replace the battery, yet still no magnetic field around the coiled wire. Perhaps the circuit has been interrupted so that no electricity will flow.
You decide that that must be it - the circuit has been interrupted - so you put it out of your mind for a while. Now a bit later in the day you have been informed that you are not alone - everybody's doorbells are the same. The electronic circuitry no longer closes an electrical loop, meaning the circuit is no longer completed - a fundamental law in nature really has changed - there is no electricity flowing, and there is no magnetic field created to enable the clapper to become magnetised.
Now here's the rub. We could arrive at the knowledge that a fundamental law of nature had changed when we learned about new causalities, but not before we'd experienced them. This is what the whole edifice of science is like – everything new is experienced, not predicted. If it can be predicted, it isn’t new, it is merely extrapolated from experience already held – and this is the brilliant legacy that Hume left us.
You may think you know of some predictions – you may have thought
that it was through
For those
who are still not convinced
If there are still some of you who are still not convinced that
without experience we would know nothing, here’s an extreme illustration I once
thought up that should help you see where you're going wrong. Imagine we
grabbed a baby boy from birth, stuck him in a room, kept him alive with food
and liquid for 18 years, but at the same time we disconnected his ability to
see, touch, taste, feel, and listen. Consider what we'd find after 18 years.
The 18 year old brain would have none of the sensory perceptions or
experiential abilities that ordinary minds have - he would be mentally
moribund, devoid of any of the concepts we have acquired through our
experiences of seeing, hearing, touching, smelling, tasting, and all the
learning that accompanies that sense data.
Now imagine that at 18 the young man is suddenly given all his senses. He gets to sense the outside world for the first time. He has no experience of anything yet, but in front of him is a billiard table and two billiard balls. He is about to be tested on causality by observing an experimenter rolling one billiard ball to hit the other (the billiard ball illustration is the one Hume uses, so for the sake of faithfulness I am using that too). Because Hume maintains that we know nothing without experience, and hence, we cannot predict anything without prior experience, he would argue that there is no way our 18 year old could have any expectation of what would happen when ball 1 hits ball 2.
An 18 year old with absolutely no prior experience is not going to have the necessary experiential capabilities to infer the billiard ball causality from ball 1 to ball 2. That is to say, it only seems obvious to us that ball 2 will move after being hit by ball 1 because we have experience of physical reality – this young man has none, so he wouldn’t know if ball 2 will roll, disappear, shatter, liquefy, melt, change colour or stay motionless. If ball 2 stayed motionless or liquefied he would have no reason to think it strange, just as a baby would have no reason to think it strange if he saw a man flying in the sky.
Hopefully these illustrations have conveyed not just a picture of Hume’s empiricist legacy, but also a clear picture of the distinction Hume made between causation (which we don’t have) and causality (which we do have), and the still relevant knowledge he gave us that there are no new predictions without prior experience.
* In his treatise Hume speaks
of the kind of cause (causality) we can know as being “An
object precedent and contiguous to another, and so united with it, that the
idea of the one determines the mind to form the idea of the other, and the
impression of the one to form a more lively idea of the other" Or
to put it another way, Hume’s notion of causality is to do with ideas built
upon a succession of activities related to how we perceive the material world,
which is an object of study that belongs within the sphere of physical science.
Wednesday, 5 February 2014
Why We Shouldn't Make A Habit Of Compensating UK Flood Victims
Tuesday, 4 February 2014
Why It *Doesn't* Pay To DIY
“I think about cluster economies and how ideally a small community could clothe itself. If you bring the idea of local and sustainable clothing production down to the person-to-person level, the realization that a small community could clothe itself is possible with reasonable expectations and a little ingenuity.”
Kelly Cobb is confused. Her project doesn't prove that local clothing production can be accomplished under reasonable expectations, it proves the opposite – it proves a whopping point against self-sufficient local trade. While extolling the virtues of making the 100 mile suit, Kelly Cobb and her team have forgotten to count the cost of staying local and making it themselves – namely the time, effort, and the cost of denying the volunteers other uses of their skills.
In fact, in the article we get an idea of the extent of the cost with this statement from Cobb:
“Creating the suit was a massive task. Nearly two-dozen artists volunteered 506 hours. “It was a huge undertaking, assembled on half a shoestring,”
Half a shoestring? That must be the world's most expensive half-shoestring. Let’s be ultra-conservative with our estimate by rounding it off to 500 hours, and let us suppose that the average hourly rate of the artists was only £15 per hour. Let us also ignore the additional travel time, fuel costs and other negative externalities associated with those 500 hours – that still works out at a whopping £7500 cost for the suit. For a twentieth of that price she could have bought a decent suit in just a few mintutes in any good clothes store - a suit that was made much more efficiently thanks to global trade, division of labour and specialisation of skills.